The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty
Rhetoric around parliamentary sovereignty and “taking back control” became a recurring theme in the Leave Campaign. But Panagiotis Doudonis argues that there is a contradiction in using a referendum – a coercive, direct democracy device – to reclaim parliamentary sovereignty, which has its foundations in representative democracy.
For months, Vote Leave argued leaving the European Union would allow Britain to retain its “constitutional identity”, but the exact nature of identity was kept vague. Ahead of the referendum this came across as an effort of “totemism”, or a mystification of the constitution as an expression of the age-old tradition of the United Kingdom.
If we could single out the dominant feature of this identity, except for the obvious point of the lack of a codified constitutional text, it would be parliamentary sovereignty. This can be summed up, in its traditional form, with the very simple rule that there is no legal limit on the legislative power of the Parliament. As Dicey put it, the Parliament “has, under the English constitution, the right to make or unmake any law whatever”.
The accession of the United Kingdom to what was then the EEC posed the question of the relationship between the sovereignty and superiority of the British Parliament on the one hand and the superiority of the European law on the other. It became clear that the belief that there are no legal limits to the legislative power of the Parliament would hardly survive or coexist with the participation in the Union. Moreover, since parliamentary sovereignty, in its classic perception, is “continuing”, i.e. “no Parliament can bind its successors”, it becomes difficult to argue that the Parliament of 1972 with European Communities Act could bind -and will continue to bind until Brexit – the Parliaments that succeed it. Lord Bridge’s observations in Factortame may have settled the issue at a legal level, but have not achieved the same at the political level.
The EU’s power over Westminster is viewed by Eurosceptics as the cornerstone of the loss of national sovereignty. Closer inspection, though, reveals logical inconsistencies and contradictions. The British constitutional identity has demonstrated the ability to adapt to new challenges. Moreover, the participation of the UK in the Council of Europe and more recently the Human Rights Act 1998, in spite of its careful wording, poses other challenges to the traditional approach to the British constitutional law and consequently to the sovereignty of Parliament.
But what does this sovereignty amount to? Its explanatory basis is based on the interconnected notions of representation and national sovereignty. Parliament is the main “bearer” of internal sovereignty -which is the other face of external sovereignty, namely the sovereignty of the United Kingdom within the bounds of international law- due to the representativeness of its dominant part, the House of Commons.
If though parliamentary sovereignty is the cornerstone of the UK constitution, a referendum aiming at the “restoration of constitutional roots” as well as Leaving the EU seem quite oxymoronic. First, referendums belong to a completely different constitutional rationale, compared to that on which parliamentary sovereignty is founded. On the one hand, we have representative, parliamentary democracy; its central expression within the bounds of the UK constitution is the superiority of the main representative institution, the Parliament. On the other hand, the referendum, as a manifestation of direct democracy, is arguably incompatible with the traditional approach of British constitutional order. As Vernon Bogdanor, David Cameron’s tutor during his Oxford years has observed, the sovereignty of parliament is a principle “generally held to preclude the referendum”.
Therefore, on the 23 June, Leave campaigners asked the British people to restore the integrity of the Parliament’s sovereignty in its absolute form through a process that is based on the opposite rationale. The contradiction continues at another level, namely the implementation of the referendum. The extent to which the vote is binding has become a major topic of discussion since the referendum. Legally, it is consultative, and no constitutional convention binds the Parliament to always follow the view expressed in a referendum. Thus, the position that a Parliament with a vast majority of pro-EU MPs is bound to decide, if asked, in favor of leaving the EU because this is the result of a referendum, epitomises the denial of the parliamentary sovereignty.
In other words, if the Parliament considers itself bound by the referendum, then it actually moves to a quasi-negation of its sovereignty, aiming at the revival of this sovereignty in its absolute and continuing form through leaving the EU. If Parliament, on the other hand, realising the complete meaning of its sovereignty, chooses to ignore the result of the referendum and decides that the United Kingdom should remain in the EU, then it actually makes an absolute statement of its sovereignty while simultaneously deciding an in perpetuo limitation to it through continued participation in the EU.
This brief analysis does not aim to make the issue seem more complicated or to express sophistry. On the contrary, it purports to point out that the absolute sanctification and totemism of the tradition of British constitutionalism is not devoid of logical and inconsistencies. What is needed though now is a new constitutionalism of truth, a new constitutional ethos of both political actors and the people based on available knowledge, revealing the polycentricity of political decisions and not hiding behind ethnocentric legalism. Otherwise, logic will be defeated and paradoxes like the aforementioned would further obscure important issues.
—
Note: this post represents the views of the author and not those of Democratic Audit or the LSE. Please read our comments policy before posting.
—
Panagiotis Doudonis holds an MJur from the University of Oxford and an LLB (Distinction) from the National and Kapodistrian University of Athens. He has practiced law both as a trainee lawyer and legal consultant in Greece. Panagiotis is currently working on his MPhil in Law at Oxford, under the supervision of Dr. Paul Yowell, Associate Professor of Law.
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/zW7b6UYe9r
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/xl6L9oTssn
@democraticaudit https://t.co/uj7JvUr5FL
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/7iMCSi8gbf
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/F8duARuH6V
Interesting, but you miss the fact that our political classes have stolen our democracy, no longer are we represented by our MP’s.
Our MP’s have been appropriated by the mainstream political parties, they are only accountable to the Whips & their parties under the fear of de-selection.
The electorate have been abandoned, hence the disconnect between them and their MP’s, the response has been a demand for referenda to correct this wrong.
https://richardcalhoun.blogspot.co.uk/2015/08/we-need-new-democracy-not-new-voting_29.html
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/xq5mbnDiou
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/bjDHcsJhJr
@democraticaudit Interesting but needs hard editing to make accessible to wider audience.
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty : https://t.co/TILL383IEO https://t.co/iyLcWBw5Cq
This is excellent: ‘The #Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty’ https://t.co/M3i17AIECl
The lack of a legal limit on the legislative power of the Parliament (ie
the right to make or unmake any law whatever) means that it has the
right to legislate inconsistently. However, in that case it is abdicating
some of its power to the judiciary who are then faced with the very
real challenge of interpretation of the law.
It is correct that no referendum is binding on Parliament (although
it may be binding on another body if parliament so legislates). This
principle does not invalidate the right of Parliament to say, in effect
“We will consider ourselves bound by this rule/principle etc UNTIL
we decide otherwise in future legislation”.
That principle is totally consistent with the doctrine of supremacy
of parliament. No change is required, needed or desirable.
Having said that the real problem is the lack of control of the
executive by the legislature. In that respect it could be argued
that the EU arrangements are more dmocratic in that the
executive (the Commission) has no control over the deciding
bodies (Council of Ministers and European Parliament as
co-decision partners) whereas the executive in UK has a
“Chief Whip” enjoined to exercise control over a majority
of the parliamentary members and a “Leader of the
Commons” to exercise formal control over the use of time
in the parliamentary arena. There is even the tradition of
a “party chairperson” being part of the executive – another
leakage of parliamentary control of the executive which has
its roots in the patronage of the First Lord of the Treasury.
None of THOSE inconsistencies are at the door of the EU
and we should get our own house (House?) in order before
putting the blame on Brussels or anywhere else in the world.
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/TKNBCe8mVh
This is excellent @democraticaudit
https://t.co/G62dtvuX5f
The Brexit paradox: Direct democracy is a flawed route to reviving sovereignty https://t.co/cBOjbTEWQh https://t.co/iCeWS3VKHN