The Brexit vote and Trump’s election were decided democratically. So why don’t they feel that way?
The Brexit referendum and Trump’s election were each decided by a free and fair vote, yet large proportions of UK and US citizens have trouble accepting them as truly ‘democratic’. A working democracy requires more than free elections; it requires additional institutions, such as well-functioning political public sphere and a responsive political party system, to channel citizens’ voices into productive public debate and foster a sense of ‘collective democratic will’, writes Brian Milstein. If these institutions are in a state of decay, democratic politics can start to appear unfocused and erratic – we can even find ourselves subject to decisions that were ‘formally’ democratic, yet somehow don’t ‘feel’ democratic, he argues.
Picture: The Prophet, via a (CC BY 2.0) licence
Since the 2016 Brexit and Trump votes, a steady chorus of commentators has pinned the problem on ‘too much democracy’: everyday citizens are just too fickle and too easily tricked by demagogues to make good decisions. When democracy is not properly reined in, minorities are left helpless against the capricious whims of tyrannical majorities. But democracy is not just a doctrine of, ‘Whatever the majority wants, it gets’.
Important as voting is to democratic decision-making, it is not the only part. Other institutions need to be in place, such as a well-functioning political public sphere and a responsive political party system. These institutions work to focus public debate, set the parameters of political disagreements, and foster a sense of collective democratic will. They make the outcomes of votes comprehensible to citizens, such that even citizens whose preferences occasionally ‘lose out’ can still understand themselves as co-participants in the decisions to which they are subject.
But decades of neoliberal hegemony have corroded the effectiveness of these institutions, and since the 2007/8 crisis, they have gradually lost their ability to productively manage public discontent. The problem is that, when these institutions break down, democratic politics can start to appear unfocused and erratic. What is striking about the Brexit and Trump 2016 votes is not simply that they marked victories for populist movements; it is that they were formally democratic decisions which the citizenries of the UK and US have been nevertheless at pains to comprehend as the product of a collective democratic will.
Take Trump, for example, who was elected with fewer votes than his opponent. In 2000, Bush was elected not only without a plurality of votes, but only after a cloud of controversy over Florida’s electoral votes and months of litigation. And yet Bush was still inaugurated into office with broad public approval, while Trump was not. Why were U.S. citizens so much more accepting of Bush than Trump, if the former’s election was more problematic on the merits?
As it turns out, voting is only one part of what makes democracy work. Citizens must be able to recognise each other as co-participants in collective political processes oriented to an idea of what is just and good for the whole. They may vehemently disagree over what is just and good for the whole, but they generally acknowledge each other’s commitments and their implications as ‘reasonable’ (if not preferable) alternatives. In diverse, complex societies, ‘collective democratic will’ means not that we share the same ideas but that we can recognise in procedures like voting faithful means for mediating among such alternatives and translating them into legitimate binding decisions.
Thus, a well-ordered political public sphere is crucial for citizens across society to familiarise each other with their respective points of view and their reasons for holding them. As a ‘semi-institutionalised’ domain, an effective public sphere must be sufficiently open and decentralised to allow citizens maximum freedom to raise new issues and identify new problems, but it must also possesses enough of an ‘infrastructure’ to bring various voices of the citizenry into contact with one another, to raise broad public awareness, and to exert pressure on centres of power.
Part of this infrastructure is provided by the political party system. The system of political parties serves as a “bridge” of sorts between the public sphere and formal voting, taking reasonable disagreements among citizens in the public sphere, repackaging them into governing philosophies, policy positions, organisational strategies, and then presenting them back to citizens as discrete ballot choices. But it also helps to structure political debate in the public sphere, centralising and sorting disagreements among citizens into a navigable range of alternative viewpoints on what is just, good, and feasible for the whole.
There is a catch here, however, because party systems tend also to foster a form of political hegemony, presenting itself and the major parties it comprises as exhausting the full range of reasonable alternatives. In normal politics, only that which one or more of the mainstream parties is willing to consider truly counts as ‘reasonable’; that which none of the parties would consider may be branded ‘extreme’, ‘fringe’, ‘pie in the sky’, or otherwise unviable.
This is a good thing, for it prevents certain kinds of extreme positions (e.g., violent or fascist) from taking hold in the mainstream political debate. But it also allows the possibility for party systems to take on ‘cartel’-like behaviours, disempowering or dismissing as ‘unreasonable’ otherwise viable alternatives from the wide public debate when they conflict with the strategic agendas of party leaders and elites.
The cartel-like evacuation from public debate of social and economic questions by major parties in the US and Europe has been widely noted, alongside accelerating inequality and the increasing influence of elites on politics at the expense of citizens. Parties cover for this narrowing of the political realm by redirecting public attention to cultural issues, personal scandals, and appeals to emotion and even prejudice, all the while upholding the narrative that they represent the only reasonable alternatives. Playing off of the market character of mass media, party elites appeal to the sensationalist impulses of commercial journalism to keep debate at a superficial level and discourage engagement with uncomfortable topics.
Some believed the 2007/8 financial crisis, with its protracted aftermath, might finally shatter the hegemony of an ossified neoliberal establishment, initiating a kind of ‘legitimation crisis‘ that re-opens the bounds of political discourse, re-energising the public sphere and paving the way for new ideas and new kinds of leaders. And it did unmoor the hegemony established parties previously held over public debate.
But the needed expansion of debate still required a sufficiently amenable public sphere. Instead, the increasing concentration of media platforms under a handful of corporate conglomerates combines with, among other things: a marketised media culture that thrives on scandal and drama as opposed to complex policy debate; increasing political activism on the part of media owners and corporate advertisers; and a culture of political journalism where success and prestige depends on ‘access’ to – and thus the goodwill of – established elites. Disenchanted as citizens may be with the established order of things, the public sphere remains excessively resistant to inputs that diverge from it.
Despite the perception that the rise of the internet and social media expand opportunities for citizen expression, the political public sphere requires means through which concerns from across society can be brought into contact with one another and tested against each other. If the public sphere as an institution fails in its ability to cypher voices from the periphery to the centre, citizens alienated from established parties in times of crisis are left with few avenues to express their concerns and mobilise as part of a society-wide process oriented to the common good. The intransigence of a hegemonised public sphere can even make it easier for charismatic figures to ‘break through’ using simplified, emotional, or sensationalistic appeals to gather support for questionable political agendas.
In this scenario, the norms of ‘reasonable’ disagreement begin to break down. Instead of a choice among political platforms addressed to the citizenry at large, the polity is confronted by factional competition among interests not oriented to the good of the whole – be they those of a discredited status quo or the populist energies of disaffected groups. This metastasised conflict is then converted mechanically through voting into binding decisions, which are formally legitimate, but which appear unreasonable or outright erratic to the citizenry at large. They no longer feel democratic.
Colin Crouch has argued that we are slowly moving from a state of democracy to one of ‘post-democracy‘, where we continue to live among the trappings of democracy, but they ‘increasingly become a formal shell’. Such a society not just undesirable; in times of protracted economic or social crisis, it is also unstable.
Since the 2007/8 crisis, major parties have been either indifferent or ineffective in channelling citizen discontent into productive public debate. In this light, it is unsurprising that many citizens have lost faith in major parties, experts, and even mainstream media institutions. The paradox is that these are the very institutions that make democratic politics coherent in the first place. If citizens perceive that major political parties are unresponsive to their needs, citizens are liable to reject the legitimacy of their leadership in framing political debate. But without a functioning public sphere, citizens cannot effectively hold parties to account or participate in the development of new alternatives for the country as a whole. What we are left with is not ‘too much democracy’, but fragmented democracy. The answer to the breaking down of democracy is not to restrict democracy, but to understand and repair the societal institutions that must come together to make it work. As citizens in the UK and the US muddle through Brexit and Trump, this is the task that lies before us.
This article gives the views of the author, and not the position of Democratic Audit. It was first published on LSE Brexit.
About the author
Brian Milstein is a Research Associate and Lecturer in International Political Theory at the Excellence Cluster “The Formation of Normative Orders,” Goethe-Universität Frankfurt.
The cry by elites that democracy needs to be ‘reined in’ (to stop it producing results the ruling class does not want) is simply what those at the top said, for example, 100 years ago when Labour made its breakthrough in the UK – ‘wicked populists…extremists’ etc etc.
Blaming the people for being in the thrall of ‘demagogues’ (a word which now means someone who believes that they say and wants to implement it) is yet another mistake and diversion from solving the real problems.
One of these is that those in power are pretty casual about lying and dissembling and believe that it has to be done to make the voters accept things they otherwise will not (so these politicians are the opposite of demagogues then, opportunist, say whatever it takes, casually lie/dissemble and use threats against the public if they dare to oppose – all in the interests of big business and a corporate state mentaility). Whatever your views on migration, for example, the major parties in the Uk simply lied about it, and about numbers…and then when they were challenged electorally on it and started to lose ground, cynically used extreme language that they had previously claimed was ‘racist’. It is OK for Labour and Tory to talk about being ‘swamped’ to win votes, but not OK for UKIP to ask that a debate be held on the issues.
To frame this entire discussion on the basis of how we can be forced to Love the Liars again is a mistake. Because of the internet and the ability to campaign without being forced to go through the gatekeepers (state media and its acolytes), this cannot happen. Every time their cloven hooves pop out, someone is there with the camera.
Unless of course what is meant by ‘reining in democracy’ is terminating it completely and allowing elected individuals no say in the running of nations…’result’, as they say, if you are the elite…but you will not get away with it.
“The Brexit Vote and Trump’s election were decided democratically”
No, no, no!
The Brexit vote was undemocratic because the voters were not fully informed. And the Leave campaign broke the law by overspending on promotion, advertising and on-line “hidden persuasion” – enough to swing the results.
Trump simply didn’t get enough votes to win. The US first past the post system is not democratic.
Tim, there was a campaign on departure and, admittedly, the Remain campaign lied and lied again as part of its Project Fear & Lie (telling us that if we dared to disobey there would be a punishment budget, and that if we even simply voted Leave there would be an immediate recession in the very next quarter and the economy would collapse, taxes would rise ‘immediately’) etc. These and other lies by Remain, however, were not effective and we cannot cancel the vote just because of the thicket of Remain failure, falsehoods and errors and inaccuracies. Similarly, when Leave made their claims about the cost of the EU, Remain simply screamed ‘lies’ without specifying the actual cost – their failure to accurately identify a figure when one had been presented to them by the other side in a campaign is their probem, not that of the voters. Simply screaming ‘liar’ is always a mistake and we can’t re-run the campaign endlessly till Remain make a decent fist of it, and stops lying…and the result goes the way they want (in which case “that’s OK then”)
On the US election – well then, try and change the system…and if you can’t, you then run a campaign based upon that system (as those who were party to it did). If you take any other route, then you will not be able to play a meaningful part in an election any time soon.